Ratzinger (1992): you cannot answer the question what man
should do until you know who man is, since doing
follows on being. But you can’t know
who man is until you know God is, since man has been made in the image and
likeness of God (Gen 1, 26). And you can’t know who God is until He tells you,
since “No one has at any time seen God. The only-begotten Son, who is in the
bosom of the Father, he has revealed him” (Jn. 1, 18).
Christ
reveals: “I and the Father are one” (Jn. 10, 30). And yet, “The Father is
greater than I” (Jn. 14, 28). Opposition of relations (relation being the
meaning of “person”) is the only way to account rationally for this disclosure
of Christ. The Relation that is the Father is to be “the act of
engendering the Son.”[1]
And the relation that is the Son is on page 1 of your
notes, equally from Ratzinger’s “Introduction…” p. 134. Read it and open your
mind to it. Everything in Christian morality – which is the morality for
everyone since Christ is the meaning of man – depends on this relational
dimension from sanctity to sex, from politics to economics.
And
then, you cannot know who Christ is unless you become Christ: “No
one knows the Son except the Father; nor does anyone know the Father except the
Son, and him to whom the Son chooses to reveal him” (Mt. 11, 27). Benedict/Francis’s
“Lumen Fidei” #36 says that “God cannot
be reduced to an object. He is subject who makes himself known and perceived in
an interpersonal relationship.” And therefore He cannot be known except
subjectively. i.e., by praying - going out self. Again, “Christ is not simply the one in whom we believe… he is also the one
with whom we are united precisely in order to believe. Faith does not merely
gaze at Jesus but sees things as Jesus himself sees them, with his own eyes: it
is a participation in his way of seeing” (#18) because it is a becoming
Him. Finally, “believers become a new creation; they receive a new being; as
God’s children, they are now "sons in the Son". The phrase
"Abba, Father", so characteristic of Jesus’ own experience, now
becomes the core of the Christian experience (cf. Rom 8:15) (#19).
What is
Moral Theology: Veritatis
Splendor: Dialogue between Jesus and the Rich Young Man. We have within us the consciousness of the good because we have an ontological
tendency within us that is
us. Go to p. 88: last 2 paragraphs of Ratzinger’s “Conscience and Truth” that grounds
the notion of the good in us ontologically. Since the Diving Person
of Christ is relational, to image Him is to be relational, i.e. to tend.
And this “tending” is what is meant by “natural law.” But notice that it is not
“nature” as “source” of activity, but the whole of the human person as imaging
the Divine Person (Son) as “Relation” to the Father.
Christ tells the rich
young man: “if thou wilt enter into life, keep the commandments” (Mt. 19, 18).
The boy responds: “All these I have
kept; what is yet wanting to me” “The commandments of which Jesus reminds the young man are meant to safeguard the good of the person, the image of God, by protecting
his goods..
‘You shall not murder; You shall not commit adultery; You shall not steal; You
shall not bear false witness’ are moral rules formulated in terms of
prohibitions. These negative precepts express with particular force the ever urgent
need to protect human life, the communion of persons in marriage, private property,
truthfulness and people’s good name.
“The
commandments thus represent the basic condition for love of neighbor; at the
same time they are the proof of that love. They are the first necessary step on the journey towards freedom, its starting
point. ‘The beginning of freedom,’ Saint Augustine writes, ‘is to be free from
crimes… such as murder, adultery, fornication, theft, fraud, sacrilege and so
forth. When once one is without these crimes… one begins to lift up one’s head
towards freedom. But this is only the beginning of freedom, not perfect
freedom…’”
It is most interesting that at this point., John Paul II
(#14) moves the gospel text from the rich young man to the lawyer who asks
similar questions but now Jesus refers him to the two commandments of love of
God and love of neighbor (Lk. 10, 25-27) “very much like the one asked by the
young man,” but now it is about the love of God and love of neighbor. And the
lawyer asks: “And who is my neighbor?” What is significant is that the
teaching moves from the morality of protecting one’s own goods, to morality of
giving them away. And it is here that there is perfection
(divinization).
VS #13 shows that the
10 commandments are the basic
condition for love of neighbor; at
the same time they are proof of that love. They are the first necessary step on the journey towards freedom, its starting
point.”
Why is love of God and neighbor inseparable? Because the
Son of God became my neighbor. God took on human flesh, the same flesh my
neighbor has. Therefore, when you do it to the least of my brethren, you do it
to me, since I am you neighbor. Notice the key to the moral theology. Morality
cannot be reduced to rules and principles because it is relation. The rich
young man: I have kept the laws and the rules but I am still not good. To be
good, I have to give myself to the poor who have Christ’s flesh. Therefore, we
keep the rules and obey the laws, but “Nescio vos,” I don’t know you.
Notice that the answer to “who is my neighbor” is:
whomever you see and come across in need is your neighbor. And notice that the
officially religious, “a certain priest” and “a Levite,” who attended and
served in the Temple and the community’s approved sacrificial rites, and both
pass him by “on the other side.” “Then comes a Samaritan, a person whom Jesus’
listeners would have identified as an enemy, a despised outsider from the
northern kingdom of Israel who did no worship at the temple. And this Samaritan
turns to the wounded one, picks him up, takes him in his arms, dresses his
wounds and brings him to an inn where he pays for his convalescence.”[2]
Moral perfection consists in self-giving. Cf. VS #17
(notes p. 12. And it is meant for everyone (#18). Note that
Moral perfection consists in loving the way God loves: “You have heard that it was said, ‘Thou
shalt love they neighbor, and shalt hate thy enemy.’ But I say to you, love
your enemies, do good to those who hate you, and pray for those who persecute
and calumniate you, so that you may be children of your Father in heaven, who
makes his sun to rise on the good and the
evil, and sends rain on the just and the unjust. For if you love those that
love you, what reward shall you have? Do not even the publicans do that? And if
you salute your brethren only, what are you doing more than others? Do not even
the Gentles do that?
[1] J.
Ratzinger, “Introduction to Christianity,” Ignatius (1990) 132.
[2] D.
Cayley “The Rivers North of the Future – The Testament of Ivan Illich” Foreword
by Charles Taylor, Anansi (2005) 50. Illich
extends the point being made in VS #14: “This doctrine about the neighbor, which
Jesus proposes, is utterly destructive of ordinary decency, of what had, until
then, been understood as ethical behavior… The Greeks recognized a duty of
hospitality towards xenoi, strangers who spoke a Hellenic language, but not towards
the babblers in strange tongues whom they called barbaroi. Jesus taught the
Pharisees that the relationship which he had come to announce to them as most
completely human is not one that is expected, required, or owed. It can only be
a free creation between two people, and one which cannot happen unless
something comes to me through the other, by the other, in his bodily presence.
It is not a relationship that exists because we are citizens of the same
Athens, and so can feel a duty towards each other, nor because Zeus also throws
his mantle over the Corinthians and other Hellenes, but because we have decided.
This is what the Master calls behaving as a neighbor.” Illich continues: “(W)e
are creatures that find our perfection
only by establishing relationship and that this relationship may appear
arbitrary from everybody else’s point of
view, because I do it in response to a call and not a category, in this the
call of the beaten-up Jew in the ditch. This has two implications. The first is
that this ‘ought’ is not, and cannot be reduced to a norm. It has a telos. It
aims at somebody, some body; but not according to a rule. It has become almost
impossible for people who today deal with ethics or morality to think in terms
of relationships rather than rules. The second implication… is that with the creation
of this new mode of existence; the possibility of its breakage also appears.
And this denial, infidelity, turning away, coldness is what the New Testament
calls sin, something which can only be recognized by the light of this new
glimmer of mutuality.”
In
the light of this, consider Ratzinger’s remark in “Dogma and Preaching” p. 9 that Christ asks far more from us in His
preaching as recorded in the Gospel than the Church can demand in rules and regulations. And consider his
(Ratzinger’s) observation that Anthony of the Desert and Francis of Assisi did
read and hear the Gospels, took it at face value (as the rich young man did
not, Mk. 10, 1), and established the canonical religious life (understood today
as “the consecrated life” involving leaving the world, and taking vows of
poverty, chastity and obedience). Until St. Josemaria, no one proclaimed the
universal call to holiness in the world and made it stick legally and
canonically in the Church. Notice that Opus Dei is a liberation from the
categories of “religious life” as state
in life with rules and regulations of that state. Rather we are free as
birds with the fulfillment of that freedom consisting in the total gift of self
to Christ (VS #85) and to the others in any state of life. The liberation of
Opus Dei is the liberation of self, and total gift to the
others.
Philosophic Development Necessary to Account For the Above:
Traditional Aristotelian anthropology was based, as we know, on the definition o anthropos zoon noetikon, homo est animal rationale. This definition fulfills Aristotle's requirements for defining the species (human being) through its proximate genus (living being) and the feature that distinguishes the given species in that genus (endowed with reason). At the same time, however, the definition is constructed in such a way that it excludes—when taken simply and directly—the possibility of accentuating the irreducible in the human being. It implies—at least at first glance—a belief in the reducibility of the human being to the world. The reason for maintaining such reducibility has always been the need to understand the human being. This type of understanding could be defined as cosmological.
others.
Philosophic Development Necessary to Account For the Above:
Subjectivity and the
Irreducible in the Human Person
Karol Wojtyla
PERSON AND COMMUNITY
Selected Essays
Translated by Theresa Sandok, OSM
(1993)
Peter Lang
15
15
Subjectivity and the
Irreducible in
the Human Being
1.
2.
3. THE STATE OF THE
QUESTION
The problem of
the subjectivity of the human being seems today to be the
focal point of a variety of concerns. It would be difficult to explain in
just a few words exactly why and how this situation has arisen. No doubt
it owes its emergence to numerous causes, not all of which should be
sought in the realm of philosophy or science. Nevertheless, philosophy—especially
philosophical anthropology and ethics—is a privileged place
when it comes to clarifying and objectifying this problem. And
this is precisely where the heart of the issue lies. Today more
than ever before we feel the need—and also see a greater
possibility—of objectifying the problem of the subjectivity of the
human being.
In this regard, contemporary thought seems to have
more or less set aside the old antinomies that arose primarily in the
area of the theory of knowledge (epistemology) and
that formed an as though inviolable line of demarcation
between the basic orientations in philosophy. The antinomy of
subjectivism vs. objectivism, along with the underlying antinomy of idealism
vs. realism, created conditions that discouraged dealing with human
subjectivity—for fear that this would lead inevitably to subjectivism.
These fears, which existed among thinkers who subscribed to realism
and epistemological objectivism, were in some sense warranted by the
subjectivistic and idealistic character—or at least overtones—of analyses conducted within the realm of "pure
consciousness." This only served
to strengthen the line of demarcation in philosophy and the opposition between
the "objective" view of the human being, which was also an ontological view (the human being as
a being), and the "subjective" view, which seemed inevitably to sever the human being from
this reality.
Today we are seeing a breakdown of that line of demarcation—and for some
of the same reasons that gave rise to it in the first place. By "some of
the same reasons" I mean that this is also happening as a result of
phenomenological analyses conducted in the realm of "pure consciousness"
using Husserl's epoché: bracketing the existence, or reality, of the conscious
subject. I am convinced that the line of demarcation between the subjectivistic
(idealistic) and objectivistic (realistic) views in anthropology and ethics
must break down and is in fact breaking down on the basis of the experience of
the human being. This experience automatically frees us from pure
consciousness as the subject conceived and assumed a priori and leads us to the
full concrete existence of the human being, to the reality of the conscious
subject. With all the phenomenological analyses in the realm of that assumed
subject (pure consciousness) now at our disposal, we can no longer go on
treating the human being exclusively as an objective being, but we must also
somehow treat the human being as a subject in the dimension in which the
specifically human subjectivity of the human being is determined by
consciousness.
And that dimension
would seem to be none other than personal subjectivity.
2. THE HISTORY OF THE QUESTION
This matter
requires a fuller examination, in the course of which wemust
consider the question of the irreducible in the human being—thequestion
of that which is original and essentially human, that which accounts for the human
being's complete uniqueness in the world.
Traditional Aristotelian anthropology was based, as we know, on the definition o anthropos zoon noetikon, homo est animal rationale. This definition fulfills Aristotle's requirements for defining the species (human being) through its proximate genus (living being) and the feature that distinguishes the given species in that genus (endowed with reason). At the same time, however, the definition is constructed in such a way that it excludes—when taken simply and directly—the possibility of accentuating the irreducible in the human being. It implies—at least at first glance—a belief in the reducibility of the human being to the world. The reason for maintaining such reducibility has always been the need to understand the human being. This type of understanding could be defined as cosmological.
The usefulness of
the Aristotelian definition is unquestionable. It became
the dominant view in metaphysical anthropology and spawned a variety
of particular sciences, which likewise understood the human being as an animal with
the distinguishing feature of reason. The whole scientific tradition concerning the composition of human
nature, the spiritual-material compositum
humanum—a tradition that came down from the Greeks through the Scholastics to Descartes—moved
within the framework of this
definition and, consequently, within the context of the belief that the essentially human is basically reducible to
the world. It cannot be denied
that vast regions of experience and scientific knowledge based on that
experience reflect this belief and work to confirm it.
On the other
hand, a belief in the primordial uniqueness of the human being,
and thus in the basic irreducibility of the human being to the natural
world, seems just as old as the need for reduction
expressed in Aristotle's definition. This belief stands at the
basis of understanding the human being as
a person, which has an equally long tenure in the
history of philosophy; it also accounts today for the
growing emphasis on the person as a subject and for the
numerous efforts aimed at interpreting the
personal subjectivity of the human being.1
In the
philosophical and scientific tradition that grew out of the definition homo
est animal rationale, the human being was mainly an object, one
of the objects in the world to which the human being visibly and physically
belongs. Objectivity in this sense was connected with the general
assumption of the reducibility of the human being. Subjectivity, on
the other hand, is, as it were, a term proclaiming that the human being's
proper essence cannot be totally reduced to and explained by the
proximate genus and specific difference. Subjectivity
is, then, a kind of synonym for the irreducible in
the human being. If there is an opposition here,
it is not between objectivism and subjectivism, but only
between two philosophical (as well as everyday and practical)
methods of treating the human being: as an object and as
a subject. At the same time, we must not forget that
the subjectivity of the human person is also something objective.2
I should also emphasize that the method of treating
the human being as an object does not result directly from the Aristotelian definition
itself, nor does it belong to the
metaphysical conception of the human being in the Aristotelian tradition. As we
know, the objectivity of the conception of the human being as a being itself required the
postulate that the human being
is 1) a separate suppositum (a subject of existence and action)
and 2) a person(persona). Still,
the traditional view of the human being as a person, which understood the person in terms of the Boethian definition
as rationalis naturae individua substantia, expressed the
individuality of the human being as a
substantial being with a rational (spiritual) nature, rather than the uniqueness of the subjectivity
essential to the human being as
a person. Thus the Boethian definition mainly marked out the "metaphysical terrain"—the dimension of
being—in which personal human
subjectivity is realized, creating, in a sense, a condition for "building
upon" this terrain on the basis of experience.
3. LIVED EXPERIENCE AS AN ELEMENT IN
INTERPRETATION
The category to which we must go in order to do this
"building" seems to be that of
lived experience. This is a category foreign to Aristotle's metaphysics.
The Aristotelian categories that may appear relatively closest to
lived experience—those of agere and pate—cannot be
identified with it. These categories serve to describe the dynamism of a being,
and they also do a good job of differentiating what merelyhappens in
the human being from what the human being does.3 But
when the dynamic reality of the human being is
interpreted in Aristotelian categories, there is in each case (including
in the case of agere and pate) an aspect not
directly apprehended by such a
metaphysical interpretation or reduction, namely, the aspect of lived experience as the irreducible,
as the element that defies reduction.
From the point of view of the meta-physical structure of being and acting, and thus also from the point of view of
the dynamism of the human being
understood meta-physically, the apprehension of this element may seem unnecessary. Even without it, we obtain
an adequate understanding of the
human being and of the fact that the human being acts and that things happen in the
human being. Such an understanding formed the basis of the entire edifice of anthropology and ethics for many centuries.
But as the need increases to understand the human
being as a unique and unrepeatable person, especially in terms of the whole
dynamism of action and inner happenings proper to the human being—in other
words, as the need increases to understand
the personal subjectivity of the human being—the
category of lived experience takes on greater significance, and, in fact, key significance. For then the issue is
not just the metaphysical objectification
of the human being as an acting subject, as the agent of acts, but the
revelation of the person as a subject experiencing its
acts and inner happenings, and
with them its own subjectivity. From the moment the need to interpret the acting human being (I'home
agissant) is expressed, the category
of lived experience must have a place in anthropology and ethics—and even somehow be at the center of
their respective interpretations.4
One might
immediately ask whether, by giving lived experience such a
key function in the interpretation of the human being as a personal subject,
we are not inevitably condemned to subjectivism. Without
going into a detailed response, I would simply say that,
so long as in this interpretation we maintain a firm enough connection
with the integral experience of the human being, not only are we not
doomed to subjectivism, but we will also safeguard the
authentic personal subjectivity of the human being in the
realistic interpretation of human existence.
1 comment:
Hello Father, do you have .pdf file for the Person and Community? I badly needed it for my research. I have limited sources of book about Karol Wojtyla. So, I'm wondering if do you have pdf files about his main works of Human Person because it will really help me in my research as well as my journey towards Priestly Vocation. Thank you.
Please send n my email:
peter15vic@gmail.com
Post a Comment